What’s so Great about Science? or, How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love Metaphysics

A couple of weeks ago, a lot people in a lot of places marched for science. What struck me about those marches is that there is almost nobody out there that is openly and explicitly campaigning against science. There are, of course, a few flat-earthers who, if one looks for them very diligently, can be found. But does anyone — including the flat-earthers themselves – think that they are serious? There are also Creationists who believe that the earth was created and designed by a Supreme Being – usually along the lines of the Biblical account in the Book of Genesis. But Creationists don’t reject science in general, they reject a particular scientific theory, because they believe it to be untrue, and try to defend their beliefs with a variety of arguments couched in scientific terms. I don’t defend Creationist arguments, but just because someone makes a bad scientific argument, it doesn’t mean that the person making the argument is an opponent of science. To be sure, the reason that Creationists make bad arguments is that they hold a set of beliefs about how the world came to exist that aren’t based on science but on some religious or ideological belief system. But people come up with arguments all the time to justify beliefs for which they have no evidentiary or “scientific” basis.

I mean one of the two greatest scientists that ever lived criticized quantum mechanics, because he couldn’t accept that the world was not fully determined by the laws of nature, or, as he put it so pithily: “God does not play dice with the universe.” I understand that Einstein was not religious, and wasn’t making a religious argument, but he was basing his scientific view of what an acceptable theory should be on certain metaphysical predispositions that he held, and he was expressing his disinclination to accept a theory inconsistent with those predispositions. A scientific argument is judged on its merits, not on the motivations for advancing the argument. And I won’t even discuss the voluminous writings of the other one of the two greatest scientists who ever lived on alchemy and other occult topics.

Similarly, there are climate-change deniers who question the scientific basis for asserting that temperatures have been rising around the world, and that the increase in temperatures results from human activity that discharges greenhouse gasses into the atmosphere. Deniers of global warming may be biased and may be making bad scientific arguments, but the mere fact – and for purposes of this discussion I don’t dispute that it is a fact – that global warming is real and caused by human activity does not mean that to dispute those facts unmasks that person as an opponent of science. R. A. Fisher, the greatest mathematical statistician of the first half of the twentieth century, who developed most of the statistical techniques now used in experimental research, severely damaged his reputation by rejecting or dismissing evidence that smoking tobacco is a primary cause of cancer. Some critics accused Fisher of having been compromised by financial inducements from the tobacco industry, while others attribute his positions to his own smoking habits or anti-puritanical tendencies. In any event, Fisher’s arguments against a causal link between smoking tobacco and lung cancer are now viewed as an embarrassing stain on an otherwise illustrious career. But Fisher’s lapse of judgment, and perhaps of ethics, don’t justify accusing him of opposition to science. Climate-change deniers don’t reject science; they reject or disagree with the conclusions of most climate scientists. They may have lousy reasons for their views – either that the climate is not changing or that whatever change has occurred is unrelated to the human production of greenhouse gasses – but holding wrong or biased views doesn’t make someone an opponent of science.

I don’t say that there are no people who dislike science – I mean don’t like it because of what it stands for, not because they find it difficult or boring. Such people may be opposed to teaching science and to funding scientific research and don’t want scientific knowledge to influence public policy or the way people live. But, as far as I can tell, they have little influence. There is just no one out there that wants to outlaw scientific research, or trying to criminalize the teaching of science. They may not want to fund science, but they aren’t trying to ban it. In fact, I doubt that the prestige and authority of science has ever been higher than it is now. Certainly religion, especially organized religion, to which science was once subordinate if not subservient, no longer exercises anything near the authority that science now does.

The reason for this extended introduction into the topic that I really want to discuss is to provide some context for my belief that economists worry too much about whether economics is really a science. It was such a validation for economists when the Swedish Central Bank piggy-backed on the storied Nobel Prize to create its ersatz “Nobel Memorial Prize” for economic science. (I note with regret the recent passing of William Baumol, whose failure to receive the Nobel Prize in economics, like that of Armen Alchian, was in fact a deplorable failure of good judgment on the part of the Nobel Committee.) And the self-consciousness of economists about the possibly dubious status of economics as a science is a reflection of the exalted status of science in society. So naturally, if one is seeking to increase the prestige of his own occupation and of the intellectual discipline in which one does research, it helps enormously to be able to say: “oh, yes, I am an economist, and economics is a science, which means that I really am a scientist, just like those guys that win Nobel Prizes.” It also helps to be able to show that your scientific research involves a lot of mathematics, because scientists use math in their theories, sometimes a lot of math, which makes it hard for non-scientists to understand what scientists are doing. We economists also use math in our theories, sometimes a lot math, and that’s why it’s just as hard for non-economists to understand what we economists are doing as it is to understand what real scientists are doing. So we really are scientists, aren’t we?”

Where did this obsession with science come from? I think it’s fairly recent, but my sketchy knowledge of the history of science prevents me from getting too deeply into that discussion. But until relatively modern times, science was subsumed under the heading of philosophy — Greek for the love of wisdom. But philosophy is a very broad subject, so eventually that part of philosophy that was concerned with the world as it actually exists was called natural philosophy as opposed to say, ethical and moral philosophy. After the stunning achievements of Newton and his successors, and after Francis Bacon outlined an inductive method for achieving knowledge of the world, the disjunction between mere speculative thought and empirically based research, which was what science supposedly exemplifies, became increasingly sharp. And the inductive method seemed to be the right way to do science.

David Hume and Immanuel Kant struggled with limited success to make sense of induction, because a general proposition cannot be logically deduced from a set of observations, however numerous. Despite the logical problem of induction, early in the early twentieth century a philosophical movement based in Vienna called logical positivism arrived at the conclusion that not only is all scientific knowledge acquired inductively through sensory experience and observation, but no meaning can be attached to any statement unless the statement makes reference to something about which we have or could have sensory experience; to be meaningful a statement must be verified or at least verifiable, so that its truth could be either verified or refuted. Any reference to concepts that have no basis in sensory experience is simply meaningless, i.e., a form of nonsense. Thus, science became not just the epitome of valid, certain, reliable, verified knowledge, which is what people were led to believe by the stunning success of Newton’s theory, it became the exemplar of meaningful discourse. Unless our statements refer to some observable, verifiable object, we are talking nonsense. And in the first half of the twentieth century, logical positivism dominated academic philosophy, at least in the English speaking world, thereby exercising great influence over how economists thought about their own discipline and its scientific status.

Logical positivism was subjected to rigorous criticism by Karl Popper in his early work Logik der Forschung (English translation The Logic of Scientific Discovery). His central point was that scientific theories are less about what is or has been observed, but about what cannot be observed. The empirical content of a scientific proposition consists in the range of observations that the theory says are not possible. The more observations excluded by the theory the greater its empirical content. A theory that is consistent with any observation, has no empirical content. Thus, paradoxically, scientific theories, under the logical positivist doctrine, would have to be considered nonsensical, because they tell us what can’t be observed. And because it is always possible that an excluded observation – the black swan – which our scientific theory tells us can’t be observed, will be observed, scientific theories can never be definitively verified. If a scientific theory can’t verified, then according to the positivists’ own criterion, the theory is nonsense. Of course, this just shows that the positivist criterion of meaning was nonsensical, because obviously scientific theories are completely meaningful despite being unverifiable.

Popper therefore concluded that verification or verifiability can’t be a criterion of meaning. In its place he proposed the criterion of falsification (i.e., refutation, not misrepresentation), but falsification became a criterion not for distinguishing between what is meaningful and what is meaningless, but between science and metaphysics. There is no reason why metaphysical statements (statements lacking empirical content) cannot be perfectly meaningful; they just aren’t scientific. Popper was misinterpreted by many to have simply substituted falsifiability for verifiability as a criterion of meaning; that was a mistaken interpretation, which Popper explicitly rejected.

So, in using the term “meaningful theorems” to refer to potentially refutable propositions that can be derived from economic theory using the method of comparative statics, Paul Samuelson in his Foundations of Economic Analysis adopted the interpretation of Popper’s demarcation criterion between science and metaphysics as if it were a demarcation criterion between meaning and nonsense. I conjecture that Samuelson’s unfortunate lapse into the discredited verbal usage of logical positivism may have reinforced the unhealthy inclination of economists to feel the need to prove their scientific credentials in order to even engage in meaningful discourse.

While Popper certainly performed a valuable service in clearing up the positivist confusion about meaning, he adopted a very prescriptive methodology aimed at making scientific practice more scientific in the sense of exposing theories to, rather than immunizing them against, attempts at refutation, because, according to Popper, it is only if after our theories survive powerful attempts to show that they are false that we can have confidence that those theories may be truthful or at least come close to being truthful. In principle, Popper was not wrong in encouraging scientists to formulate theories that are empirically testable by specifying what kinds of observations would be inconsistent with their theories. But in practice, that advice has been difficult to follow, and not only because researchers try to avoid subjecting their pet theories to tests that might prove them wrong.

Although Popper often cited historical examples to support his view that science progresses through an ongoing process of theoretical conjecture and empirical refutation, historians of science have had no trouble finding instances in which scientists did not follow Popper’s methodological rules and continued to maintain theories even after they had been refuted by evidence or after other theories had been shown to generate more accurate predictions than their own theories. Popper parried this objection by saying that his methodological rules were not positive (i.e., descriptive of science), but normative (i.e., prescriptive of how to do good science). In other words, Popper’s scientific methodology was itself not empirically refutable and scientific, but empirically irrefutable and metaphysical. I point out the unscientific character of Popper’s methodology of science, not to criticize Popper, but to point out that Popper himself did not believe that science is itself the final authority and ultimate arbiter of scientific practice.

But the more important lesson from the critical discussions of Popper’s methodological rules seems to me to be that they are too rigid to accommodate all the considerations that are relevant to assessing scientific theories and deciding whether those theories should be discarded or, at least tentatively, maintained. And Popper’s methodological rules are especially ill-suited for economics and other disciplines in which the empirical implications of theories depend on a large number of jointly-maintained hypotheses, so that it is hard to identify which of several maintained hypotheses is responsible for the failure of a predicted outcome to match the observed outcome. That of course is the well-known ceteris paribus problem, and it requires a very capable practitioner to know when to apply the ceteris paribus condition and which variables to hold constants and which to allow to vary. Popper’s methodological rules tell us to reject a theory when its predictions are mistaken, and Popper regarded the ceteris paribus quite skeptically as an illegitimate immunizing stratagem. That describes a profound dilemma for economics. On the one hand, it is hard to imagine how economic theory could be applied without using the ceteris paribus qualification, on the other hand, the qualification diminishes empirical content of economic theory.

Empirical problems are amplified by the infirmities of the data that economists typically use to derive quantitative predictions from their models. The accuracy of the data is often questionable, and the relationships between the data and the theoretical concepts they are supposed to measure are often dubious. Moreover, the assumptions about the data-generating process (e.g., independent and identically distributed random variables, randomly selected observations, omitted explanatory variables are uncorrelated with the dependent variable) necessary for the classical statistical techniques to generate unbiased estimates of the theoretical coefficients are almost impossibly stringent. Econometricians are certainly well aware of these issues, and they have discovered methods of mitigating them, but the problems with the data routinely used by economists and the complicated issues involved in developing and applying techniques to cope with those problems make it very difficult to use statistical techniques to reach definitive conclusions about empirical questions.

Jeff Biddle, one of the leading contemporary historians of economics, has a wonderful paper (“Statistical Inference in Economics 1920-1965: Changes in Meaning and Practice”)– his 2016 presidential address to the History of Economics Society – discussing how the modern statistical techniques based on concepts and methods derived from probability theory gradually became the standard empirical and statistical techniques used by economists, even though many distinguished earlier researchers who were neither unaware of, nor unschooled in, the newer techniques believed them to be inappropriate for analyzing economic data. Here is the abstract of Biddle’s paper.

This paper reviews changes over time in the meaning that economists in the US attributed to the phrase “statistical inference”, as well as changes in how inference was conducted. Prior to WWII, leading statistical economists rejected probability theory as a source of measures and procedures to be used in statistical inference. Haavelmo and the econometricians associated with the early Cowles Commission developed an approach to statistical inference based on concepts and measures derived from probability theory, but the arguments they offered in defense of this approach were not always responsive to the concerns of earlier empirical economists that the data available to economists did not satisfy the assumptions required for such an approach. Despite this, after a period of about 25 years, a consensus developed that methods of inference derived from probability theory were an almost essential part of empirical research in economics. I close the paper with some speculation on possible reasons for this transformation in thinking about statistical inference.

I quote one passage from Biddle’s paper:

As I have noted, the leading statistical economists of the 1920s and 1930s were also unwilling to assume that any sample they might have was representative of the universe they cared about. This was particularly true of time series, and Haavelmo’s proposal to think of time series as a random selection of the output of a stable mechanism did not really address one of their concerns – that the structure of the “mechanism” could not be expected to remain stable for long periods of time. As Schultz pithily put it, “‘the universe’ of our time series does not ‘stay put’” (Schultz 1938, p. 215). Working commented that there was nothing in the theory of sampling that warranted our saying that “the conditions of covariance obtaining in the sample (would) hold true at any time in the future” (Advisory Committee 1928, p. 275). As I have already noted, Persons went further, arguing that treating a time series as a sample from which a future observation would be a random draw was not only inaccurate but ignored useful information about unusual circumstances surrounding various observations in the series, and the unusual circumstances likely to surround the future observations about which one wished to draw conclusions (Persons 1924, p. 7). And, the belief that samples were unlikely to be representative of the universe in which the economists had an interest applied to cross section data as well. The Cowles econometricians offered to little assuage these concerns except the hope that it would be possible to specify the equations describing the systematic part of the mechanism of interest in a way that captured the impact of factors that made for structural change in the case of time series, or factors that led cross section samples to be systematically different from the universe of interest.

It is not my purpose to argue that the economists who rejected the classical theory of inference had better arguments than the Cowles econometricians, or had a better approach to analyzing economic data given the nature of those data, the analytical tools available, and the potential for further development of those tools. I only wish to offer this account of the differences between the Cowles econometricians and the previously dominant professional opinion on appropriate methods of statistical inference as an example of a phenomenon that is not uncommon in the history of economics. Revolutions in economics, or “turns”, to use a currently more popular term, typically involve new concepts and analytical methods. But they also often involve a willingness to employ assumptions considered by most economists at the time to be too unrealistic, a willingness that arises because the assumptions allow progress to be made with the new concepts and methods. Obviously, in the decades after Haavelmo’s essay on the probability approach, there was a significant change in the list of assumptions about economic data that empirical economists were routinely willing to make in order to facilitate empirical research.

Let me now quote from a recent book (To Explain the World) by Steven Weinberg, perhaps – even though a movie about his life has not (yet) been made — the greatest living physicist:

Newton’s theory of gravitation made successful predictions for simple phenomena like planetary motion, but it could not give a quantitative account of more complicated phenomena, like the tides. We are in a similar position today with regard to the strong forces that hold quarks together inside the protons and neutrons inside the atomic nucleus, a theory known as quantum chromodynamics. This theory has been successful in accounting for certain processes at high energy, such as the production of various strongly interacting particles in the annihilation of energetic electrons and their antiparticles, and its successes convince us that the theory is correct. We cannot use the theory to calculate precise values for other things that we would like to explain, like the masses of the proton and neutron, because the calculations is too complicated. Here, as for Newton’s theory of the tides, the proper attitude is patience. Physical theories are validated when they give us the ability to calculate enough things that are sufficiently simple to allow reliable calculations, even if we can’t calculate everything that we might want to calculate.

So Weinberg is very much aware of the limits that even physics faces in making accurate predictions. Only a small subset (relative to the universe of physical phenomena) of simple effects can be calculated, but the capacity of physics to make very accurate predictions of simple phenomena gives us a measure of confidence that the theory would be reliable in making more complicated predictions if only we had the computing capacity to make those more complicated predictions. But in economics the set of simple predictions that can be accurately made is almost nil, because economics is inherently a theory a complex social phenomena, and simplifying the real world problems to which we apply the theory to allow testable predictions to be made is extremely difficult and hardly ever possible. Experimental economists try to create conditions in which this can be done in controlled settings, but whether these experimental results have much relevance for real-world applications is open to question.

The problematic relationship between economic theory and empirical evidence is deeply rooted in the nature of economic theory and the very complex nature of the phenomena that economic theory seek to explain. It is very difficult to isolate simple real-world events in which economic theories can be put to decisive empirical tests that allow us to put competing theories to decisive tests based on unambiguous observations that are either consistent with or contrary to the predictions generated by those theories. Under those circumstances, if we apply the Popperian criterion for demarcation between science and metaphysics to economics, it is not at all clear to me whether economics is more on the science side of the line than on the metaphysics side.

Certainly, there are refutable implications of economic theory that can be deduced, but these implications are often subject to qualification, so the refutable implications are often refutable only n principle, but not in practice. Many fastidious economic methodologists, notably Mark Blaug, voiced unhappiness about this state of affairs and blamed economists for not being more ruthless in applying Popperian test of empirical refutation to their theories. Surely Blaug had a point, but the infrequency of empirical refutation of theories in economics is, I think, less attributable to bad methodological practice on the part of economists than to the nature of the theories that economists work with and the inherent ambiguities of the empirical evidence with which those theories can be tested. We might as well just face up to the fact that, to a large extent, empirical evidence is simply not clear cut enough to force us to discard well-entrenched economic theories, because well-entrenched economic theories can be adjusted and reformulated in response to apparently contrary evidence in ways that allow those theories to live on to fight another day, theories typically having enough moving parts to allow them to be adjusted as needed to accommodate anomalous or inconvenient empirical evidence.

Popper’s somewhat disloyal disciple, Imre Lakatos, talked about scientific theories in the context of scientific research programs, a research program being an amalgam of related theories which share a common inner core of theoretical principles or axioms which are not subject to refutation. Lakatos called these deep axiomatic core of principles the hard core of the research program. The hard core defines the program so it is fundamentally fixed and not open to refutation. The empirical content of the research program is provided by a protective belt of specific theories that are subject to refutation and, when refuted, can be replaced as needed with alternative theories that are consistent with both the theoretical hard core and the empirical evidence. What determines the success of a scientific research program is whether it is progressive or degenerating. A progressive research program accumulates an increasingly dense, but evolving, protective belt of theories in response to new theoretical and empirical problems or puzzles that are generated within the research program to keep researchers busy and to attract into the program new researchers seeking problems to solve. In contrast, a degenerating research program is unable to find enough interesting new problems or puzzles to keep researchers busy much less attract new ones.

Despite its Popperian origins, the largely sociological Lakatosian account of how science evolves and progresses was hardly congenial to Popper’s sensibilities, because the success of a research program is not strictly determined by the process of conjecture and refutation envisioned by Popper. But the important point for me is that a Lakatosian research program can be progressive even if it is metaphysical and not scientific. What matters is that it offer opportunities for researchers to find and to solve or even just to talk about solving new problems, thereby attracting new researchers into the program.

It does appear that economics has for at least two centuries been a progressive research program. But it is not clear that is a really scientific research program, because the nature of economic theory is so flexible that it can be adapted as needed to explain almost any set of observations. Almost any observation can be set up and solved in terms of some sort of constrained optimization problem. What the task requires is sufficient ingenuity on the part of the theorist to formulate the problem in such a way that the desired outcome can be derived as the solution of a constrained optimization problem. The hard core of the research program is therefore never at risk, and the protective belt can always be modified as needed to generate the sort of solution that is compatible with the theoretical hard core. The scope for true refutation has thus been effectively narrowed to eliminate any real scope for refutation, leaving us with a progressive metaphysical research program.

I am not denying that it would be preferable if economics could be a truly scientific research program, but it is not clear to me how much can be done about it. The complexity of the phenomena, the multiplicity of the hypotheses required to explain the data, and the ambiguous and not fully reliable nature of most of the data that economists have available devilishly conspire to render Popperian falsificationism an illusory ideal in economics. That is not an excuse for cynicism, just a warning against unrealistic expectations about what economics can accomplish. And the last thing that I am suggesting is that we stop paying attention to the data that we have or stop trying to improve the quality of the data that we have to work with.

10 Responses to “What’s so Great about Science? or, How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love Metaphysics”


  1. 1 Jason Smith May 10, 2017 at 12:00 am

    “Climate-change deniers don’t reject science; they reject or disagree with the conclusions of most climate scientists. They may have lousy reasons for their views … but holding wrong or biased views doesn’t make someone an opponent of science.”

    This doesn’t capture the real problem. The real problem is that these people lack what Paul Romer called “Feynman integrity” in a blog post awhile back – leaning over backwards to consider how you could be wrong. It’s not just holding incorrect views, but holding them without attempting to confront the idea that they might be the ones in error. The scientists in the IPCC reports are constantly questioning their own results. Climate change deniers do not. I think they think being skeptical of the consensus is enough to show this integrity, but it isn’t. This lack of introspection kills science; if science was to become a set of opinions about data where no one ever considered that they might be wrong the whole edifice collapses. That’s why there is peer review: to force scientists of all disciplines to consider they might be wrong. If a reviewer tells you you’re wrong and you don’t entertain that possibility, your paper will be rejected. Op Eds don’t quite operate in the same way, and that’s why climate “skepticism” proceeds mainly through political journalism than scientific journals.

    As an aside: it isn’t so much that Einstein thought quantum mechanics was wrong; he thought there had to be more to it. This wasn’t really proven until after Einstein’s death (Bell’s theorem and the experimental evidence following it), and many other physicists thought there might be a more fundamental theory in Einstein’s day. In a sense, even though they turned out to be right, the physicists who thought the “randomness” of quantum mechanics was fundamental could be considered going out on a limb. Previously everyone though Newtonian physics was everything. Then along comes Heisenberg et al, and they’re saying Newtonian physics is incomplete but their new theory covers everything. Einstein also showed that Newtonian physics wasn’t everything. Together, they just proved one paradigm that was though to be all encompassing to be incomplete. Why would you think the new paradigm would be complete?

    Like

  2. 2 Nick Rowe May 10, 2017 at 3:18 am

    Very good post. Sensible.

    Like

  3. 3 Lord May 10, 2017 at 2:46 pm

    I also disagree climate deniers aren’t rejecting science. While some will hide their certainty behind uncertainty, their arguments are climate scientists are politically motivated, doing this to further their funding, or for status. They don’t generally argue over science at all, only what they believe, and their demands for ending funding are focused on areas where they don’t like the results. This is a rejection of science.

    Like

  4. 4 kaleberg May 10, 2017 at 5:27 pm

    That’s the problem with science. It’s a method, not a result. When you start making exceptions about the method whenever you don’t like a result, then you are against science. When Einstein expressed his reservations about quantum theory, he nonetheless accepted the result. He had hopes, as so many others did back then, that further investigation would provide some way of eliminating the element of randomness in the theory. This never happened, and the random element has proven to be central to our understanding. Einstein had no problem with the method and accepted its results.

    When a creationist rejects evolution or the theory that the earth is more than four thousand years old, they reject both the results, but also the method. They argue that one can learn the age of a tree by counting and measuring the rings, but carve out a special case for learning the age of a rock or a bone or even a fossilized tree. That is anti-science. When a climate change denier rejects the fact that the climate has been changing and that humans have anything to do with it, they are rejecting not just the result, but the method.

    As with quantum theory, there was a time when it was possible to question climate change and whether humans had anything to do with it. There were all sorts of alternate theories, as there were with quantum mechanics, but as more data was collected and measurements and analytic techniques improved, it became increasingly clear that the world is getting warmer, and we humans have a lot do to do with it. Unless there is an entire realm of data we have somehow missed or some complex mechanism which has not yet been conceived of, then we are stuck the with conclusion: climate change is real.

    Now, it is possible to stay skeptical about a theory well past that skepticism’s sell-by date, but doing so within the scientific method would require accepting what has been learned, but arguing that there are places we haven’t looked and ideas that haven’t been tried. That’s not what creationists and climate change deniers do. They argue that all the fossils, all the dating methods, all the genetic evidence are irrelevant, that the entire method based on them is unacceptable, and that the truth shall be determined by the text of a two thousand year old book. They argue that all the temperature measurements, the ice cores, the altered growing seasons, the changing composition of the atmosphere, what we’ve learned from weather and climate modeling are irrelevant, and that the truth shall be determined by the economic desires of certain wealthy corporations and individuals. That’s anti-science.

    This schizophrenia is sometimes laughable. NOAA has been under pressure to improve its weather forecasting, at least to the levels obtained by the Europeans. Amusingly, this means that the climate change denying Republicans in Congress have passed legislation requiring NOAA to incorporate forecasting code validated in modeling and predicting climate change. That is, the science behind studying climate change is good, good enough for a ship to sail or a farmer to plant, but not acceptable in determining that we need to do something serious about the warming climate.

    Like

  5. 5 Andrew_M_Garland May 10, 2017 at 9:14 pm

    ** Lying for the Cause

    I support science, the process of careful data collection and experiment followed by a transparent release of data, computer code, and plain argument. Real science is sceptical. It rejects fuzzy argument and unsupported or unverifiable claims. Experience shows that anything less leads to costly error.

    Claims about catastrophic global warming rely on a few facts about carbon dioxide and direct warming, and a pile of speculation, models, and government manipulation. Most of climate science is not science. Publishing only a graph is scientifical, not science. I think of the Hockey Stick here.

    I trust in results produced by a group of skeptical and independent scientists attempting to disprove/improve on the theories floating around. Government climate scientists embrace one result but not one model, and they obscure the data leading to their conclusions. That is a cabal, not a scientific community.

    It is ridiculous to trust in the integrity of a “scientific community” or “peer review” where prominent members of academic and government institutions announce they are willing to lie for the good of the peasants.

    The models are complex, Dr. Mann won’t release his data, and manipulations of peer-reviewed, published graphs to “hide the decline” are explained as unfortunate limitations of space. The people who push Climate Change (was: Global Warming) only have the credibiility of their data and methods.

    One might argue that any exaggerations are only a few. If so, why aren’t the rest denouncing them, proclaiming proudly that the data is what counts, proclaiming that exaggeration and lying are not needed? Their silence demeans the global warming community and its science.

    ( http://pjmedia.com/eddriscoll/2012/03/03/unless-we-announce-disasters-no-one-will-listen/ )
    Lying for climate change
    3/3/12 – Ed Driscoll [edited]
    === ===
    It is a fascinating development when people admit that they are lying for their cause.

    –> Prof. Chris Folland, Hadley Centre for Climate Prediction and Research
    “The data doesn’t matter. We’re not basing our recommendations on the data. We’re basing them on the climate models.”

    –> Dr David Frame, Climate modeler, Oxford University
    “The models are convenient fictions that provide something very useful.”

    –> Paul Watson, Co-founder of Greenpeace
    “It doesn’t matter what is true, it only matters what people believe is true.”

    –> Sir John Houghton, First chairman of the IPCC
    “Unless we announce disasters no one will listen.”

    –> Christine Stewart, former Canadian Minister of the Environment
    “No matter if the science of global warming is all phony … climate change provides the greatest opportunity to bring about justice and equality in the world.”
    === ===

    ** Skeptical Science

    There are many, different climate models published by the IPCC. Where is the skepticism of science expressed? Are there any papers within the IPCC which criticize other papers or models?

    ** Useful Research Predicts the Future

    The late Particle Physicist Richard Feynman explained what a true scientist does. Everything else is opinion or manipulation, wearing the cloak of science without the integrity that produces true results.

    Cargo Cult Science
    1974 by Richard P. Feynman – Commencement speech at CalTech
    http://www.lhup.edu/~DSIMANEK/cargocul.htm

    === ===
    [edited] Details that could throw doubt on your interpretation must be given, if you know them. You must do the best you can to explain them, if you know anything at all wrong or possibly wrong.

    If you make a theory, for example, and advertise it, or put it out, then you must also put down all the facts that disagree with it, as well as those that agree with it. There is also a more subtle problem.

    When you have put a lot of ideas together to make an elaborate theory, you want to make sure, when explaining what it fits, that those things it fits are not just the things that gave you the idea for the theory; but that the finished theory makes something else come out right, in addition.
    === ===

    I don’t see the climate science community doing this, and especially not the IPCC. I see the cloak of science without attention to the details and criticisms.

    Like

  6. 6 AlanDownunder May 20, 2017 at 5:14 pm

    It is a mistake to liken the the various metaphysics underpinning the “science”s of economics to some alleged metaphysics that underpins science. This is the kind of mistake that underpins climate denialism.

    Like

  7. 7 Lalluq May 22, 2017 at 10:00 pm

    My perception is that we entirely frame wrong our dear economic phenomenon. We frame economics like it would be trees, or cellular biology, or whatever other natural phenomenon that functions by some preestablished rules and in a more or less established context, rules and context that in any given time we may know more or less about. Meanwhile, in real life, ‘economics’ is about the life of the group.

    And here is where the first problem arise, groups are very different among them, in multiple ways, if compared among them in any given moment, and at times get to be different compared in themselves at different periods or stages. So we can’t have by default an ‘economic theory’, there needs to exist more economic theories :). Is pretty much like one would wanna compare a cow with a horse only because both stand on 4 feet, and then they would lament that the horse didn’t give the milk and the cow didn’t fare well at war. So an economic theory that may have some validity for a group in a certain period may not have any validity whatsoever for another group in the same moment, or for the same group in another moment, or may have less validity. I know, sounds terrifying, not at all encouraging or simple, but this is the truth. Hence, we probably need to depart from the question what is that a group of people and their life. We would nevertheless accept the reality that each group of people is a collection of families ultimately. The problem is not all the groups of people relate the same to the concept of family, or have the same concept of family, or have similar family life, just to begin with, so for example we formulate a theory which says that every individual will pursue his own interest, except for quite a number of countries and for quite a share of the planet individuals pursue the interests, wishes, and ideas, of just anyone else, generally the father, or the man, or just anyone else older and most often male. Then, we assume that if the interest of some is one particular interest, that would be the same interest for the neighbour even when they do have the same family concept and life, and then we are a bit puzzled that it wasn’t pretty much like that in real life. Just as examples. We formulate ideas regarding the real estate market for example, including its relstionship with the balanace of payment and as such the banking system, and so on, but we don’t take into account that some nations have 60% property and some over 90%, we don’t take into account the age of the people, etc., we just formulate ideas and based on them make policies pure and simple, and of course a type of disequilibria or another happens if we try to apppy the same policies. So, without trying to know a bit ourselves, in any given moment, and without developing ideas and ways each group in its own courtyard without ignoring what the neighbour is doing of course, we will continuously create ‘man made disasters’ with economic and monetary policy. So probably we can have a common goal, but we can’t reach it all in the same manner or in the same time, and others simply can’t reach it for the moment. For instance, just as another example, we talk about balance of payment crises and all alike for our world, and we formulate all sort of theories and solutions to the problem, but then you get in the Arab world, where they are full of maids and drivers and others alike whom by default produce nothing but consume, they are some sort o parasites de facto, so how exactly do our theories derived from our life, or solutions derived from our problems and world, apply there?, when summarized turns out that the more money the nation makes, the more bankrupt they end up as a nation, with really spectacular deficits given their numbers and context combined with the money they made from fossils, because people en masse, mainly almost all the women, plus entire legions of maids, drivers, and others alike, are de facto parasites under the sun, all together fully believing in their model of life, it blows whatever theory we have about economics, nobody ever saw such a thing, the more money you make, the more underdeveloped you are and the more you remain behind in comparative terms regarding gathering of human capital and as such social capital, and the more unsustainable and poor you become speaking in abstract. And the examples can go on, even in different type of cultures or places, which simply don’t show like they would follow the mainstream Western economic various big currents even when they are applied. So, probably for the beginning we should start by acknowledging that humans are neither trees nor cattles, but a different form of beings, and although we become more predictable in groups, it is for sure we don’t have the same life, on the same level, in the same time, so ‘economics’ simply can’t be the same for everybody, or the same for the same nation but on different curves or in different social regimes. Probably here is were the West missed even at home, although the social environment changed in the last decades, the economic ideas remained the same as in times when they were a solution for those problems and a way for that society, except now there is a different society in more respects, and there are different problems, but the economic thinking largely remains anchored in the past. Certain ideas remain valid, but not all. Certain ideas are as valid for us as they were for the sumerians thousands of years ago, but others not.

    And then, there is another problem, we want to relate to monetary policy as in the times of the currency, although nowadays the societies function till a degree on a form of ‘electronic barter’, we are heading away from the currency toward a more ‘clearing’ so to call it system of ‘barter’, but we don’t quite realize it or talk about it. We will also move more from a system of ‘the big employers’ to a more small clusters system of life, more artisanat, more individual enterprising, and others alike, with the advance of the new technologies, which create different opportunities for individuals and families than during the ‘classic industrialisation era’ so to speak, and depending on the social culture, number of the group, heritage, the groups would start to adhere to and adopt more and more othrr ways to satisfy some needs, I see it with clothes making and others alike more and more in my nation for example, these big textiles will suffer a blow at a certain point in the future, an this is just one example, but we don’t have theories for such a type of world but more like for feudalism in different forms :).

    So is for sure economics will never be the science of the trees, but is also for sure that we may operate with wrong ideas in wrong contexts, and also with obsolete ideas and views in other contexts, and mostly having in mind a background that may become more obsolete in the future, and then we may end up saying ‘the operation was a success but the patient is dead’. Regarding monetary policy, indeed we have 2700 years of ‘the currency’, and I don’t know how ready are we, intellectually speaking, for the ‘semi-barter’ system that we seam to be heading toward, and this including political science, philosophy, and other fields, not only economics. 🙂

    But the best news is that economics as a field does have a future, a great future, and will continue to attract great minds, even more multilaterally developed and prepared than in the past, only because the reasons I said above, it may even become less boring and push for an evolution of the tools used as well, because as long as there will be humans, there will be policy and trade, and as such economics :). So may sound a bit like a paradox, but although seams like the end for the economists, I think is just the beginning, and complexity is after all a reality in all matters and as such shouldn’t scare the economists if even this field will be somehow ‘hit’ by it :).

    Like

  8. 8 Lalluq May 22, 2017 at 10:27 pm

    As another example. Personally, I don’t quite understand how ECB can continue making monetary policy as we know it as a science, I was looking inside the portfolios of the banking systems per country, they have quite different exposures, quite different styles, and is not like in US where a bank has a presence in multiple states, largely they have each one their own banking system in practical terms, and they depart from different situation, and have different exposures, and different needs, and can’t even exit euro because they are overly exposed one on another among those countries. And I don’t even add the rest of EU countries which nevertheless always are exposed and at times hitted by the ECB due to all the connections. So by default whatever rule or policy you pursue, a country or another will get hit somehow. Probably we need to entirely invent a new way to make monetary policy. The good news is that after all this is how groups of people evolve, we are pushed by circumstances to first accept we have a problem and then to search for some way of solving it. So we shouldn’t dispair at all if the old ways don’t work or aren’t fitted anymore. And who knows, may be is exactly this which makes economics a trye science, who imagined the mathemstics of today during Cardano for example?!, they didn’t imagine not even what he was doing. So may be this is a science afterall, and we just have the wrong attitude toward it.

    Like

  9. 9 David Glasner May 25, 2017 at 6:17 pm

    Sorry for the long hiatus in responses to readers’ comments.

    Jason, I agree that Feynman integrity is a wonderful attribute, but I don’t think it is a uniquely scientific attitude. I think that lawyers, philosophers, metaphysicians, theologians and all sorts of other people are capable of making good faith arguments and trying to fair to those against whom they are arguing, trying to argue against the strongest possible version of the opposing point of view, not the weakest. What makes a statement scientific is not the frame of mind of the person making the statement but some objective property of the statement, i.e., whether it excludes some potentially observable state of the world. The law of gravity is a very precise statement about the behavior of bodies of mass with respect to each other, so it excludes a huge number potentially observable states of the world such as the water in an open bottle moving sideways when I turn it upside down. That has nothing to do with how a physicist would respond to someone who questioned the validity of the law of gravity.

    My point about quantum mechanics is that a scientific theory can be motivated by a general feeling about how the universe works, a feeling that doesn’t have to be scientific in the sense that it could be refuted by an observation or by evidence. Einstein wasn’t comfortable with intrinsic randomness in the universe, so that motivated him to posit a certain kind of theory. Someone else might not accept the idea that the diversity of life on this planet is simply the result of random genetic mutations, and would therefore posit some sort of non-Darwinian account of the diversity of observed life forms. What makes the resulting theories scientific or non-scientific is not the motivation for the theory but the relationship of the theory to observable states of the world.

    Nick, Thanks.

    Lord, Climate change deniers may or may not be rejecting science. I am simply saying that someone’s rejection of a scientific consensus is not ipso facto proof that science as such is being rejected.

    Kaleburg, Sometimes a result can be interpreted one way in one theoretical paradigm an another way in a different theoretical paradigm. Galileo had to convince people that their sensory perception of a flat motionless earth was not an incontrovertible fact, but a mistaken perception. So just because a creationist denies what you consider to be an empirical fact doesn’t necessarily mean that the creationist is denying science. He may simply be positing a different paradigm (or world view) within which empirical facts are understood in a different way from how they are understood in a different paradigm. Now there are only so many degrees of freedom in the way in which empirical facts can be understood in a paradigm or worldview. Ultimately the paradigm may fall apart because there are too many inconsistencies or implausible hypotheses that must be accepted for the paradigm to avoid self-contradiction or incoherence, but it is not necessarily impossible to carry it off.

    Andrew, Thanks for your input. If you are expecting me to defend climate science and proponents of climate change and global warming, I must disappoint you, because I try not to say much, and if possible nothing at all, about subjects that I know nothing about and climate science is one of them.

    AlanDownuder, Sorry, but your point seems too subtle for me to grasp.

    Lalluq, Thanks.

    Like


  1. 1 Friday links: how to handle bad reviews, zombie ideas in conservation, and more | Dynamic Ecology Trackback on May 12, 2017 at 4:00 am

Leave a comment

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.




About Me

David Glasner
Washington, DC

I am an economist in the Washington DC area. My research and writing has been mostly on monetary economics and policy and the history of economics. In my book Free Banking and Monetary Reform, I argued for a non-Monetarist non-Keynesian approach to monetary policy, based on a theory of a competitive supply of money. Over the years, I have become increasingly impressed by the similarities between my approach and that of R. G. Hawtrey and hope to bring Hawtrey’s unduly neglected contributions to the attention of a wider audience.

My new book Studies in the History of Monetary Theory: Controversies and Clarifications has been published by Palgrave Macmillan

Follow me on Twitter @david_glasner

Archives

Enter your email address to follow this blog and receive notifications of new posts by email.

Join 3,271 other subscribers
Follow Uneasy Money on WordPress.com